A typical example is pollution of air, water or soil, were the pollution is the unintended by-product of production which affects the value of the resource to other users or enjoyers, but which is not accounted for in the markets for either the production inputs and factors, or the markets for the products of the production process. Other relevant examples are pretty countrysides and wildlife, which are largely a consequence of farming practices in the UK, either producing these "by-products" or not, depending on the practices adopted.
These external effects are important because they mean that market transactions do not account for all the benefits and costs of particular activities, so the outcome of markets cannot ensure a social optimum. They arise because of two major factors:
We can picture the situation as in the following diagram.
The
point of private profit maximisation is Qm. At this point (and
corrpsonding
production activity), the damage suffered by the river users and
enjoyers
is very substantial. On the other hand, there is a level of production
and associated production practice which would eliminate the pollution
entirely (shown by the intersection of the MD curve with the horizontal
axis - implying in this illustration that some level and form of dairy
farming is actually beneficial to the river environment).
Suppose that the farmer owns the river, and is alive to the business opportunities of the river. It might be worth his while to find out how much people were prepared to pay for enjoying or using the river. The answer would be that they would only be prepared to pay for a cleaner and less polluted river. The marginal damage (MD) curve shows how much they would be prepared to pay for a cleaner river, reading this curve from right to left, since it shows the monetary equivalent of the damage they suffer from the polluted river. They would be prepared to pay up to this damage suffered to avoid it (prefering to pay less of course). The sensible farmer would then negotiate with the potential users, agreeing to take steps to reduce pollution so long as the price paid for a cleaner river were greater than the reduction of net revenue earned from the farming operation as a result of reducing pollution. This reduction is shown by the MC curve, again reading from right to left. The final agreement between farmer and user would be at Q* pollution, with a payment of T* per uint of cleaner river by the users to the farmer.
What if the farmer does not own the river? Suppose the river is owned by someone else, who is also concerned about its value to them and other users. In this case, these owners can require the farmer to take steps not to damage their resource, and to pay compensation to the owners if such damage occured. The compensation required by the owners is shown, again, by the MD curve (reading from left to right) - a little compensation for a small amount of pollution and a lot for a large amount. What would now be the farmer's best option? Think, before you read on.
The farmer increases his private net revenues the more pollution he causes, but at a reducing rate, as shown by the MC curve, left to right. But he is now required to pay for this pollution at an increasing rate, according to the MD curve, left to right. The profit maximising optimum for the farmer is now where the reducing marginal benefit of polluting (the MC curve) crosses the increasing marginal cost to him of polluting - the MD curve. Once again, the market equilibrium solution (the optimum) is at pollution level Q* and the farmer paying T* per unit of pollution to the owners for the priviledge of polluting the river.
Conclusions on externalities
Thus, according to these principles, there does exist a logic which would allow for negotiations between owners and beneficiaries of a resource and polluters or damagers of (in effect using up) this resource to agree on an appropriate transaction and contract which balances the interests of the producers and users - allowing some pollution, but preventing levels of pollution where the gain from additional pollution is less than the cost of this additional pollution. In effect, our marginal damage curve above is the marginal social cost of pollution, while the marginal cost curve is the marginal social benefit of pollution.
This last remark might raise some eyebrows. The marginal net benefit of private production, however, is also a social benefit (reflecting the market demands for the product in question, milk and beef in this case). Of course, we can object that these markets are distorted by government policies and intervention, and thus do not properly reflect the social benefit of dairy farming. Quite right. The analysis above assumes that the markets for the products produced with pollution are perfectly competitive and not distorted.
The analysis also points up the often very serious difficulties with externalities. Three of the most important are as follows.
It is partly because of these difficulties, and also because the
effects of pollution (or, more generally, environmental degradation)
tend
to be
specific to particular locations and different between different
locations and practices (that is, the effects are highly
heterogeneous),
that governments are asked (by their electorates, assisted by pressure
groups) to intervene and find solutions to the externality problems.
This
analysis suggests that the appropriate solution is a system of
pollution
taxes or subsidies to avoid degradation. It can be shown that, under
restrictive
conditions, the tax/subsidy system is more efficient than
regulation
- blanket restrictions on levels of pollution and fines/penalties for
contravention
of the regulations (see here
for a demonstration of this conclusion, and reasons why regulation
might, nevertheless, be a preferable option in many cases, as is
frequently
observed in public opinion preferring regulation to taxes and
subsidies).