ACE8015.
Market
Failures
Public Goods and
Externalities &
the Market Roles of Government
The most important forms or types of Market Failure
affecting rural resources and the environment are:
- Public Goods
-which are
not like private goods (most of the ones we mostly think of) because,
once
public goods are produced or provided, they are available to everyone.
- Externalities -
which are
the (largely) unintended by-products or side-effects of production (or
consumption) which are not accounted for in market transactions.
Both of these conditions mean, as we shall see, that
the social (communal or collective) costs or benefits of an
economic
activity are not the same as the sum of private costs and benefits as
accounted
for in market transactions. The consequence is that the market can no
longer
be relied upon to generate a socially optimal allocation of resources
to
different forms of output, and hence cannot provide an optimal mix of
end
products. What do I mean by "socially optimal"? That mix of
products
which properly reflects everyones' desires and wants, added up
according
to their willingness to pay, such that no one can be made better
off
without simultaneously making someone else worse off - the Pareto
Principle for judging economic welfare.
Of course, this gives rise to another major reason for government
intervention
and regulation of the market system: to alter and affect the distribution
of
income and wealth which the market generates, and the distribution of
the
economic activity which goes with it over the territorial space of the
community - geographical distribution - so that the less well off have
a greater weight (more income and/or more say) in determining what is
produced
(and where). Remember the JUDGE function of governement at the
beginning
of this course (explained in the reference chapter for session
1)?
The Government as 'Judge' determines fair and just distributions of
income,
wealth, purchasing power, command over goods and services etc.
However,
economics has nothing to say about the exercise of this function, other
than to point out that any practical re-distribution typically reduces
the efficiency of the market system by distorting the economic signals
encouraging people to economise on scarce resources and adopt the most
productive and efficient systems.
Remember the two other key functions of government? Policeman
- already implicit in the workings of the market system, since laws of
contract and property rights are essential for markets to function. Pharmacist/Mechanic
- which we have already seen something of under the heading of
regulation
of imperfect competition and monopoly, and under Macroeconomics - since
this function
is about making markets work better (that is, more efficiently -
getting
more out for what we put in). Some brief
concluding
remarks are provided in this section on the pros and cons of the
market
system, which should tie in with the opening
part
of the course. In addition, these notes also link to the Climate Change Issue
- and the question of Cost Benefit Analysis (CBA)
1. Public Goods
For private goods (or services), my
consumption,
use or enjoyment denies you the use of the same unit - so my demand for
the good or service competes with yours - we rival each other
for
the use of the product. The total demand for private goods is therefore
the sum of the quantities each of us wishes to purchase at each price -
we add up individual demand curves horizontally along the quantity
axis.
<>For Public Goods, however, my use,
consumption
or enjoyment does not deny you the use, consumption or
enjoyment
of the good - we are not rivaling each other for the use of the good
(or
service), so they are non-rival in consumption. An example is a
football game or theatre performance - where, if anything, the more
people
who are enjoying or watching the performance, the greater the enjoyment
of each person. So, how might we think if the total demand for a
football
game or theatre performance? Instead of adding up the quantity (1 or
the
length or the performance, game) for each person, we need to add up the
price
each
person is willing to pay for the performance - we add up individual
demands
vertically,
up the price axis, accumulating the total amount the audience is
willing
to pay for the same performance.
This example, however, illustrates that
"non-rivalness"
is not the only characteristic which separates public goods from
private
goods. In these cases, it is simple and easy to exclude people from the
game or performance - we can stop people who have not paid from getting
into the ground or theatre, and exclude them. For a public good,
however,
this is not possible - public goods are non-excludable as well
as
being non-rival. Examples include street lighting, lighthouses,
national
defence, public health (cleaner air, disease control etc.,) radio and
TV
broadcasts [though note here that it is possible, and now increasingly
inexpensive, to
exclude people - or at least fine them if they do not have the
appropriate
receiver license), and, importantly, the natural (or urban)
environment.
There are also such things as public bads - pollution is the classic
example,
which we will deal with below.
The market problem of public goods and a
possible
solution.
Why is the non-excludable
characteristic a
problem?
Because if private (non collective) companies or organisations cannot
charge
people for their use, how are they going to raise enough revenue to pay
the costs of providing these public goods? They cannot, other than
relying
on charitable (altruistic) donations from people who care about these
goods.
So, a simple-minded economist (who believes that people only do things
for their own narrow self-interest) might argue that these public goods
can never be provided by a free market. An "economically rational"
individual
would not spend hard earned income on public goods, since s/he would
reason
that others will provide the good anyway, and cannot exclude him or her
from consumption or enjoyment once they do, so there is no point in
contributing
- better to "free-ride" on other (less economically rational)
peoples'
charity. If everyone behaved like this, no-one would get any public
goods. Economics is, indeed, a dismal science.
There must be something wrong here, though.
People
do organise themselves
to provide for at least some public goods. The
lighthouses
in the UK are run by Trinity House, which is an independent (private)
organisation,
paid for by contributions from mariners. The Royal National Lifeboat
Institution
(RNLI) is similarly a private charity supported solely by voluntary
donations.
Public service television stations in the US also exist and are
succesful
on the same principle. A lot of people are not quite so narrow-minded
and
stupidly selfish as the purely self-interested economically rational
man
- thank goodness.
Nevertheless, free-riding is a problem for many
public
goods. Unless everyone is forced to make a contribution (through
taxes),
the chances are that less of the public good will be provided
than
is socially optimal - that is, less than everyone is really
willing
to pay for the good, and hence a smaller or lower supply of the good
than
everyone really wants. Thus, many public goods are paid for
and provided by the Government, through coercion on the public's (yours
and my) behalf. What do we mean by socially optimal?
Imagine, as a simple case, two people
(households)
interested in getting streetlights put into their private street (of
just
two houses). Both households have their own ideas about how much they
are
willing to pay for this common (public) service. One household (the
most
interested) could discover how much streetlighting would cost, and
realise
that it alone was not willing to pay the full amount. It might then
approach
the other and ask for a contribution towards the total cost. What would
be the outcome of such negotiations?
The following diagram explains this and shows how
(honest) negotiation between people could provide for the right amount
of the public good that people want. This diagram may look
seriously
off-putting - but it is really quite straightforward - spend a little
time
and thought following through the explanation in the boxes - just get
your
brains into gear! The outcome is that both households each
contribute
what they are willing to pay for street lights, and the combined amount
is enough to cover the costs of supplying the amount (number) of
streetlights
that both households (collectively) are willing to pay for. This
is socially optimal for this community of two households. If the
costs were greater than the households willingness to pay, then too
many
street lights would be provided. If the costs were lower than the
combined
willingness to pay, then too few lights would be provided, since the
users
are colectively willing to pay for more.

The major problems with this concept of voluntary
collective negotiation for the supply of public goods should be obvious
(with a little thought). The solution requires that all the people
interested
in and benefiting from the public good are fully committed to the idea
of collective action, and recognise that the solution will not work if
people free-ride. This might be expected amongst a relatively small and
coherent community (such as mariners for lighthouses and the RNLI for
instance).
Otherwise, as with the Royal Society for the Protection of Birds
(RSPB),
which (among other things) buys or rents wildlife reserves for the
conservation
of birds and thus related environments - as public goods -with
voluntary
donations and subscriptions, the organisation must put up with the
near-inevitability
that there will be substantial free-riding. Although the RSPB can, of
course,
exclude all but it own members from particular wildlife reserves, the
general
public cannot be excluded from the general good of encouraging
wildlife.
The National Trust is another example, albeit helped by the Her
Majesty's
Treasury in that large estates or country houses etc. can be left to
the
National Trust in lieu of estate duties, which would otherwise accrue
to
the Treasury as taxes.
Although the formal logic of this solution
suggests
that each contributor will pay a different price according to their own
willingness to pay, the difficulties with this differential pricing
solution in
practice normally result in a standard contribution (membership fee,
annual
subscription etc.), though always allowing for the seriously altruistic
or enthusiastic to contribute more if they like.
In some cases, it may be that a particularly rich
or concerned member of the public might be prepared to pay for the
public
good on their own. This would follow from the above diagram if Dy intersected
the supply curve (at C=MC=AC) - then the intersection would
indacate
the quantity Y would buy on his/her own, without support from the rest
of the community. There is one classic case of this - the American
media
tycoon Ted Turner was so impressed with public service broadcasting
(PSB,
no adverts) that he bought his own PSB station in his home city of
Atlanta.
Once he had done so, of course, he was able to raise additional
voluntary
contributions from other residents, and thus extend the quality of the
service. But this is a non profit making enterprise.
In general, however, for many public goods
(National
Parks, Environmentally Sensitive Areas, Areas of Outstanding National
Beauty,
national defence) it has been considered that the problem of
free-riding
is too great, and these public goods are provided by the Government and
paid for out of general tax revenue, to which everyone is obliged to
contribute
according (roughly) to their means. This,
of course, requires some idea of how much people
are actually willing to pay for the public goods in question,
otherwise how does the government know how much of them to provide and
how much to spend making them available?
See here for a short
aside on the meaning of income elasticities for public goods.
Merit Goods (also
publicly provided)
There is another class of goods (and especially
services)
provided from the public purse, though not principally because
they
are public (non-rival, non-excludable) goods. These merit goods -services
- education, health service are classic examples, are
considered
by the public through their governments to be sufficiently important to
everyone that they should be provided to all independently of their own
ability or willingness to pay.
The issue here is that the market mechanism is
capricious
in the income (and wealth) distribution that it generates between
people.
The accidents of birth, personalities, family circumstances and local
conditions
all combine with the operation of the market system itself to ensure
that
incomes are never equal. Although most governments seek to rectify this
somewhat with social security and progressive taxation systems (where
the
rich are supposed to pay more than the poor), the fact remains that
some
people will be richer than others, and thus have a generally greater
willingness
to pay. Social justice and equity demand, however, that some things are
too important to be left to the market (even given that the poor are
supported
through income supplements of various sorts). For those interested, a thought-piece
by your lecturer on the NHS might provoke some intelligent comment?
There are, however, some clear overlaps between
merit
goods and public goods. Some of our public goods (especially, perhaps,
the natural environment in the form of National Parks etc.) are also
considered
to be merit goods. Our major merit goods (health, education) also have
public good aspects - the better educated and the more healthy the
population,
the better-off everyone is, regardless of the indivudal level of health
or education of each of us, simply because the economy and society is
likely
to work and perform better.
Nevertheless, it is helpful to keep the public
good and merit good arguments separate when considering the
problems of (for example) provision for conservation of the natural
environment,
or issues of the health and education services.
2. Externalities
Externalities arise when the activity of one
person, household or firm causes a loss or a gain to another, and where
these losses or gains are uncompensated or unrewarded. If the
gain
or loss effects are comensated or rewarded, then we have a normal
market
transaction - externalities are those effects which are outside
(external
to) the market mechanisms of payments and contracts.
A typical example is pollution of air, water or
soil,
were the pollution is the unintended by-product of production which
affects
the value of the resource to other users or enjoyers, but which is not
accounted for in the markets for either the production inputs and
factors,
or the markets for the products of the production process. Other
relevant
examples are pretty countrysides and wildlife, which are largely a
consequence
of farming practices in the UK, either producing these "by-products" or
not, depending on the practices adopted.
These external effects are important because they
mean that market transactions do not account for all the
benefits
and costs of particular activities, so the outcome of markets cannot
ensure
a social optimum. They arise because of two major factors:
- first, transactions costs - the
necessary transactions
to account for the benefits and costs (to internalise the effect within
a market mechanism) are difficult and expensive in time and effort;
- second, because the property rights
to
pretty
countrysides or wildlife are unclear or contested - who owns the
landscape
or view, or the wildlife? Without clear ownership rights, there is no
legitimate
basis for the negotiations about rewarding benefits or compensating
losses.
Take as an example the case of pollution of a river
by some production system (a dairy farm, if you like). If the farmer
can
produce without regard to the pollution he causes, he will maximise his
private profits, since pollution control will generally cost money and
reduce margins. There is, then, some upper bound to the level of
pollution
that this production activity will cause, consequent on the private
profit
maximising behaviour of the dairy farm. However, this level of
pollution
may well kill all the wildlife in the river, through atrophication.
This
damage will affect anglers, wildlife enthusiasts, water users
downstream,
ramblers etc., who value cleaner rivers and the benefits they enjoy
from
cleaner rivers.
We can picture the situation as in the following
diagram.
The
point of private profit maximisation is Qm. At this point (and
corrpsonding
production activity), the damage suffered by the river users and
enjoyers
is very substantial. On the other hand, there is a level of production
and associated production practice which would eliminate the pollution
entirely (shown by the intersection of the MD curve with the horizontal
axis - implying in this illustration that some level and form of dairy
farming is actually beneficial to the river environment).
Suppose that the farmer owns the river, and is alive to the business
opportunities of the river. It might be worth his while to find out how
much people were prepared to pay for enjoying or using the river. The
answer
would be that they would only be prepared to pay for a cleaner and less
polluted river. The marginal damage (MD) curve shows how much
they
would be prepared to pay for a cleaner river, reading this curve from
right
to left, since it shows the monetary equivalent of the damage they
suffer
from the polluted river. They would be prepared to pay up to this
damage
suffered to avoid it (prefering to pay less of course). The sensible
farmer
would then negotiate with the potential users, agreeing to take steps
to
reduce pollution so long as the price paid for a cleaner river were
greater
than the reduction of net revenue earned from the farming operation as
a result of reducing pollution. This reduction is shown by the MC curve,
again reading from right to left. The final agreement between farmer
and
user would be at Q* pollution, with a payment of T* per
uint
of cleaner river by the users to the farmer.
What if the farmer does not own the river? Suppose the river is
owned
by someone else, who is also concerned about its value to them and
other
users. In this case, these owners can require the farmer to take steps
not to damage their resource, and to pay compensation to the owners if
such damage occured. The compensation required by the owners is shown,
again, by the MD curve (reading from left to right) - a little
compensation
for a small amount of pollution and a lot for a large amount. What
would
now be the farmer's best option? Think, before you read on.
The farmer increases his private net revenues the more pollution he
causes, but at a reducing rate, as shown by the MC curve, left to
right.
But he is now required to pay for this pollution at an increasing rate,
according to the MD curve, left to right. The profit maximising optimum
for the farmer is now where the reducing marginal benefit of polluting
(the MC curve) crosses the increasing marginal cost to him of polluting
- the MD curve. Once again, the market equilibrium solution (the
optimum)
is at pollution level Q* and the farmer paying T* per unit of pollution
to the owners for the priviledge of polluting the river.
Conclusions on externalities
Thus, according to these principles, there does exist a logic which
would allow for negotiations between owners and beneficiaries of a
resource
and polluters or damagers of (in effect using up) this resource to
agree
on an appropriate transaction and contract which balances the interests
of the producers and users - allowing some pollution, but preventing
levels
of pollution where the gain from additional pollution is less than the
cost of this additional pollution. In effect, our marginal damage
curve
above is the marginal social cost of pollution, while the
marginal
cost curve is the marginal social benefit of pollution (arising
because of the useful and valuable things which are produced, but which
also result in pollution).
This last remark might raise some eyebrows. The marginal net benefit
of private production, however, is also a social benefit (reflecting
the
market demands for the product in question, milk and beef in this
case).
Of course, we can object that these markets are distorted by government
policies and intervention, and thus do not properly reflect the social
benefit of dairy farming. Quite right. The analysis above assumes that
the markets for the products produced with pollution are perfectly
competitive
and not distorted.
The analysis also points up the often very serious difficulties with
externalities. Three of the most important are as follows.
- First, it is often very difficult to estimate the monetary
equivalent
of the damage caused by pollution (or equivalently, the value of
cleaner
environments - more diverse wildlife and and more valuable landscapes
etc.).
Voluntary donations to organisations such as the RSPB strongly suggest
that there is a large demand amongst at least some of the general
public
for cleaner and more natural environments. It might be that, in
particular
circumstances, the MD curve in the above diagram lies everywhere above
the MC curve, in which case the market (economic) optimum level of
pollution
would be zero (that level of production which does not damage the
environment
at all). In other cases, however, it could be that the actual
willingness
to pay exhibited by the general public for cleaner environments is
simply
insufficient to outweigh the indirect benefits of pollution (the value
of the production and associated consumption). A case in point is
traffic
pollution - generally, the public is concerned to reduce this, but is
not
prepared to do without all the indirect benefits of traffic pollution.
So we try to insist that research and development is devoted to making
our "necessary" traffic cleaner (shifting the MC curve to the left),
and penalising only those who cause
excessive
pollution, rather than everyone.
- Second, there are often very considerable transaction and
negotiation
costs associated with getting everyone concerned with the problem
together
and reconciling their differences. Frequently this is because the
externality
has at least some of the properties of being also a public good - like
better environments, cleaner air and rivers etc. But, even where this
is
not the case, the fact that the side-effect has not already
been
accounted for in market transactions and remains an externality itself
implies that the costs and effort required to undertake the necessary
transactions
are too great to be worthwhile. Externalities are, therefore, an
indication
that the transactions necessary to internalise them are more costly
than
the benefits which might be obtained from carrying out the
transactions.
The existence of organisations like the RSPB illustrate the market
response
- try and develop institutions and organisations to reduce the
transactions
costs and negotiate collective agreements to reduce negative (bad)
externalities
and encourage positive (good) externalities.
- Third, the ownership of the property rights on the
natural
resource
is often contested. Who should pay for pollution depends on who owns
the
affected resource or property, as shown above. The notion that farmers
should be subsidised (paid) to avoid polluting the natural environment
implies that farmers own the natural environment. If they do not, then
the implication is that farmers should be taxed (required to pay
compensation)
for any pollution they cause. The general presumption (outside
agriculture)
is that air, water, and even soil are common property - belonging to
everyone
- so the polluter pays principle applies. Should farmers be
different,
and if so, why? Thoughtfull and well argued Answers
to me, please!
It is partly because of these difficulties, and also because the
effects of pollution (or, more generally, environmental degradation)
tend
to be
specific to particular locations and different between different
locations and practices (that is, the effects are highly
heterogeneous),
that governments are asked (by their electorates, assisted by pressure
groups) to intervene and find solutions to the externality problems.
This
analysis suggests that the appropriate solution is a system of
pollution
taxes or subsidies to avoid degradation. It can be shown that, under
restrictive
conditions, the tax/subsidy system is more efficient than regulation -
blanket restrictions on levels of pollution and fines/penalties for
contravention
of the regulations (see here for a demonstration
of this conclusion, and reasons why regulation might, nevertheless,
be a preferable option in many cases, as is frequently observed in
public
opinion preferring regulation to taxes and subsidies).
Further Thoughts on Externalities and
Public Goods:
Arising from an EU research programme on Animal Welfare (EconWelfare)
which I become involved with recently. [Reference:
EconWelfare report, from which these notes
come (see, also, a companion report on
international trade implications)]
Two major questions arise:
- Is Animal Welfare a Public Good?
- Why don't people pay for improved animal welfare through the
animal products they buy? (Or, what are the reasons for the apparent
gap between votes (opinion poll surveys) in favour of improved animal
welfare and the actual spending on improved AW products?)
[Exactly similar questions might be asked about quite a lot of
environmental goods and services (ecosystem services)]
While the conditions of animal welfare are, perhaps, a public good
to the extent that whatever conditions of welfare exist, they exist for
everyone, and no-one can be excluded, the conditions are not indivisible - all sorts
of different animal welfare conditions exist, and the conditions which
currently prevail are the consequence of two factors:
- The (public/government) regulations on minimum animal welfare
conditions in the various producing countries and supply chains (and
the extent to which these regulations are enforced)
- The extent to which consumers pay for products associated with
improved (better) AW
AW (Environmental) Regulations
are the consequence of an ongoing political debate and decision-making
process (what Stefan Mann calls a 'deliberative process') - , which
essentially arbitrates between Animal Welfare advocacy groups on the
one hand and producer interests on the other, since improved animal
welfare (over and above what is commercially prudent) generally adds to
production and supply costs, and reduces competitiveness versus less
regulated suppliers. Unless consumers are willing to remain loyal to
the products from better (more stringently regulated) animal welfare
suppliers, i.e. willing to actually spend to improve welfare, they will
take their business elsewhere, and the market will tend to 'race to the
bottom' - attempts to improve animal welfare at home (beyond what
domestic and other consumers are actually willing to pay for) simply
export animal ill-fare abroad. Hence, regulations can be expected
to provide a minimum and most commonly acceptable level of animal
welfare at home - and it is the regulation which is the public good,
rather than the levels of animal welfare per se. Regulation
failure happens (in principle, and ceteris paribus) if consumer
spending on local animal products fails to increase by at least enough
to cover the costs of meeting (and policing) improved regulatory
standards, following the introduction of the higher AW regulations -
though this test might be very difficult to execute in practice, since
the ceteris paribus
conditions do not hold and are difficult to control for. In short,
delegation of authority to politicians and government regulation for
improved animal welfare does not abdicate citizens from their
responsibilities as consumers to legitimise and justify the regulations
on their behalf.
Consumers versus Citizens choices and
intentions: it is frequently observed that citizens
'votes' (repsonses to opinion poll surveys, or even to more
sophisticated contingent valuation surveys or choice experiments) do
not necessarily correspond to their actual purchasing behaviour -
people do not generally put their money where their mouths are, either
for animal welfare or, more generally, for environmental (CARE) goods
and services. Why not? There are several sensible and
justifiable answers, most of which do not constitute market
failure. This suggests that the possibility of regulatory failure
is high (since, if there is no reason to suppose market failure, then
regulations which intervene in the market process will 'fail' in the
sense that society as whole would be better off in economic welfare
terms without the imposed regulation).
The possible reasons for a citizen/consumer gap - a difference between
voting or opinions about AW (or the environment) and spending patterns:
There are, in principle, six major
reasons that can be attributed to people ‘voting’ for animal
welfare improvements (expressing or reporting attitudes in favour of
better animal welfare) but not actually purchasing more animal welfare
friendly products, as shown in the Figure below.
The simplest (first)
reason/excuse is that people are not actually prepared to pay the
necessary premium for the more AW friendly products. Whatever their
reasons, which are doubtless extremely complex, it is simply ‘cheap talk’ to vote for something
for which one is not prepared to pay. If consumers to not exhibit or
express any WTP for AW friendly products, markets cannot be expected to
work. The fact that markets do not respond to attitudes or votes cannot
be described, in itself, as ‘market failure’.
However, there are several other reasons which can explain the
difference between attitudes and exhibited WTP (i.e. actual purchase
decisions). The second
reason identified in the Figure is that (some) people would be willing
to pay the necessary premium if only they could be sure that their
contribution to improved animal welfare would actually make a
difference to animal welfare – one aspect of the free-rider problem. Since they
cannot be sure that enough other people will pay enough to generate
their preferred levels of welfare (environment), there is a reduced
incentive for them to contribute themselves. The other, more common,
aspect is that self-interested people will rely on others to pay the
necessary premium, and simply free-ride on the outcome. In total
(summed over the relevant population) the shortfall between peoples’
willingness to pay on their own account, and the amounts they would be
willing to pay if they were convinced that their own spending was also
matched by others, can be termed the ‘free-rider deficit’.
In principle, if this deficit is greater than the amount necessary to
encourage the supply or marketing chain to deliver the associated
improvement in animal welfare (the ‘market deficit’), then society
would be better off if the free-rider problem could be solved. On the
other hand, if the free-rider deficit is not greater than the market
deficit, then although there is a potential free rider problem, it does
not result in any
market failure – society would not be better off by
‘solving’ the problem – the costs of doing so would outweigh the
benefits.
In practice, it is observed (e.g. Verbeke, 2010) that some people do
appreciate the social pressures and norms encouraging them to spend
their own money on improving animal welfare – hence both implicitly
recognising and also dealing with the free-rider problem. “Some consumers reported a strong intention
of purchasing sustainable dairy products, despite weak personal
attitudes towards them. The explanation was found in those consumer’s
social environments, where social pressure from peers acted as a
purchasing motive. However, growing numbers of consumers are
translating their citizen interest in animal welfare into purchasing
intentions” (ibid. p 327). In effect, these people consider
themselves part of a club or society in which the social pressures and
norms are sufficient to persuade them to conform in spite of, rather
than because of, their own self-interests. As societies spend more time
and effort considering the present state of and possibilities for
improving animal welfare, so people become more aware of the issues and
more likely to respond to growing social pressures to support efforts
to improve animal welfare. This ‘involvement’ of consumers with the
products and their provenance, either directly or indirectly through
social norms, can be improved, for some segments of the market, by
improved communication and information, which effectively encourage
people to join the ‘virtual’ clubs of those concerned about animal
welfare. In short, simple economics, which assumes everyone is purely
self-interested and rational, suggests that the free-rider problem
could be substantial. In the real world, in which very few are simple homus economicus, and in which many
are responsive to their peers and social norms, the free-rider problem
may not be as significant. Social norms and values can certainly be
cultivated and encouraged through active debate and provision of
objective, disinterested information and validation services, which
need to be provided through collective and collaborative action
(governance), if not at public expense - an aspect of information and
communication as a genuine public good.
[A practical and important aside: Actually measuring the
free-rider deficit is fraught with serious, if not overwhelming,
difficulty. It necessarily involves measuring willingness to pay as a
pre-condition, and subsequently identifying the differences between
this estimate with and without the condition that others are also both
willing to and actually do pay their ‘share’. Since the questions
eliciting peoples’ WTP are necessarily hypothetical – applying to
conditions and circumstances which do not presently exist – the answers
are always subject to hypothetical bias – people do not actually do
what they say they will do, because ‘other things are not (and never
are) equal’. Some analysts have gone so far as to argue that this
hypothetical bias is sufficiently strong as to render all such
‘contingent valuation’ exercises effectively meaningless (e.g. Diamond
and Hauseman, 1994). Others, e.g. Blamey et al., 1995, argue that
people express different preferences for public (or club) goods than
for private (normal) goods, and that the two sorts of preferences (and
the associated decisions) are necessarily and conceptually distinct and
non-commensurate – termed the ‘citizen hypothesis’. However, Curtis and
McConnell (2002) using data involving preferences for deer culling
programmes in the US, demonstrate that the citizen hypothesis is
observationally equivalent to the ‘standard’ self-interested hypothesis
augmented to include altruism. As Curtis and McConnell (ibid) note: “The citizen hypothesis is not empirically
testable. It is a maintained hypothesis because the citizen hypothesis
concerns the individuals' underlying motives and these motives are
never conclusively revealed in actual behaviour or survey responses
(p 72).
These authors go on to note that: “The
impetus for the eco-labelling movement comes from the potential for
individuals to combine their preferences for private and public goods.
The consumption of all market goods has implications for the community,
be it through employment, government services, morals or some other
avenue. Altruistic motives provide a rational explanation of why
self-interested people make choices that appear to be more beneficial
to the community than to the individual. At least in the case we have
studied, there is no difference in the WTP for respondents who could be
reasonably classified as citizens and consumers" (p 81/2)].
Whether or not any substantial free-rider problem actually exists for
animal welfare in Europe cannot simply be inferred from a difference
between attitudes in favour of animal welfare and actual purchases of
animal friendly products. The citizen-consumer gap also depends on the
other reasons why citizens’ ‘voting’ (attitudes) in favour of improved
animal welfare are not matched by their purchases as consumers.

The third reason (see Figure)
is that the labelling of animal welfare friendly products is not
sufficiently obvious or reliable to attract consumers or to convince
them that their additional spending will have the desired effect of
encouraging improved welfare. The fourth
reason is closely related - that the information available to consumers
about animal welfare and the improved standards used in producing some
products is insufficient (or too contradictory or confusing) for them
to make an informed choice.
The appropriate remedies for each condition are obvious: improve the
provision of disinterested (objective) information; use (disinterested)
third party validation against proven standards; develop better and
more reliable labelling procedures. Many retailers consider that,
while animal welfare standards are an interesting market niche, animal
welfare as a stand-alone attribute is difficult to market separately
from other quality characteristics, such as compliance with
environmental standards or biodiversity, or organic production methods
and systems. Nevertheless, especially in the UK, the Netherlands and
Sweden, multiple retailers have already instituted animal welfare
standards as part of their ‘premium’ product lines. The GLOBALgap
standard, although not specifically identified on product labels, is
increasingly being integrated into retailers supply chain management
and branding. However, it is difficult for the concerned consumer (or
their representatives and champions) to discover what these standards
actually mean, since they are not (presently) always in the public
domain. Furthermore, governments themselves may not always be
considered the most reliable or credible sources of disinterested
information, or the most effective communicators, and there is a clear
role for third parties (including NGOs) in improving information and
communication about animal welfare conditions and concerns (which might
well qualify for public fund assistance on information and
communication public good grounds). In addition, “consumers
may use mistrust in information as an excuse of their unwillingness to
change their purchasing behaviour in line with their alleged concerns”
(Toma et al., 2011, p. 263), who go on to conclude from their study
that their "results
suggest that if a consumer is provided with adequate labelling of pork
produced on farms certified to voluntarily not use gestation crates, we
find no economic support justifying a ban on the use of gestation
crates on the grounds of improving general consumer welfare.”
(p. 724).
Tonsor and Wolfe (2011) also examine the question of whether or not
labelling should be mandatory, rather than voluntary. "When
initially asked, 61.7% and 62.0% (of the sample of 2001 US consumers)
indicated they would be in favor of mandatory labeling of pork produced
on farms using gestation crates and of eggs produced using laying hen
cages, respectively. .. When follow-up questions directly referencing
price implications were asked, many participants removed their support
for mandatory labeling. In particular, 44.5%, and 43.8% of those
supporting mandatory labeling of gestation crate and laying hen cage
use, respectively, in the initial question, reversed their position and
opposed the referendum when presented with price increases"
(p432). Their conclusions from this study provide a good summary
statement of present socio-economic understandings of the issues: “Much
research remains that would further improve our understanding of
underlying demand (both of voters and meat consumers) for farm animal
well-being, the implications for livestock producers, and the ultimate
appropriateness of alternative regulatory environments in setting
standards for the treatment of farm animals and the provision of such
information to the general public" (p 435).
Improved communications, information and more reliable animal welfare
labels, while obvious and useful, may not necessarily narrow the gap
between attitudes and actions substantially. The fifth and sixth
reasons for the disparity between reported attitudes/stated preferences
and actual behaviour are probably more important (e.g. Verbeke, 2009).
The fifth reason: If
consumers have to spend valuable time and energy searching for animal
welfare friendly products, then the effective price of improved animal
welfare rises and the demand falls. Similarly, if other things
(taste,
quality, safety, convenience) are more important than the welfare
provenance, then consumers will ration their time, effort and money in
favour of these more important attributes, and not bother to seek out
specific animal welfare friendly products.
The sixth reason: Moreover,
consumers (and citizens) are not only concerned about their food – they
have plenty of other things to be interested in, worried and concerned
about, and on which to spend their time, effort and money. They will,
in other words, tend to be ‘rationally ignorant’ – not bothering to
spend time and effort trying to find out about, or to find, animal
welfare friendly products in the face of all their competing interests
and (pre-) occupations. The benefits they would get from the effort are
simply not worth it to them, though their responses in surveys will
often be revealed as ‘being unable to find welfare friendly products’
and is often ascribed to be due to a ‘lack of availability’. It is also
likely that at least some people would prefer not to be reminded about
animal welfare at all when shopping for food. As a consequence, “Improved
farm animal welfare is more likely be realised and valued by consumers
when it is integrated within a broader concept of quality, such as
quality assurance or sustainability schemes” (ibid, p.
325).
Notice that both attitude surveys and typical WTP studies, being
focused on the specific issue of animal welfare, in isolation from the
real world, do not
include these real world constraints and considerations, and are always
and necessarily biased in favour of the focussed issue as a
result.
Isolated attitudes are not likely to be reliable indicators of purchase
intentions or actions, as is frequently found in the literature.
Considering all the potential reasons why consumers’ behaviour might
well differ from their stated attitudes (‘votes”) in favour of animal
welfare as citizens, it should come as little surprise that there is a
gap between attitudes and behaviour. Indeed, what is perhaps more
surprising is that the gap is not larger. The apparent gap does not
necessarily justify specific government action to bridge the gap, but
the analysis of the reasons for the gap does indicate the roles, and
likely effectiveness of information, communication, verification,
disinterested standard setting and associated labelling support
activities, and also indicate that public-private partnerships are
likely to prove most effective.
3.
Concluding
Remarks on the market system.
The issue of environmental conservation (and its
opposite
- pollution and degradation) shows that the market system evolves and
develops
in response to changing supply and demand conditions. Immediately after
the second war, people in the UK were much more concerned about food
security
than about the natural environment, and agriculture was encouraged and
supported almost regardless of the consequences for the environment
(which
was largely treated as a free good).
As concerns over food security diminished, and
people
became richer and more leisured, so the demands for countryside and
wildlife
increased (witness the growth in membership and subscription to the
environmental
and wildlife pressure groups and action organisations like the RSPB).
So,
too, does public support for the policies of agricultural protection
and
subsidy diminish, leading to changes in the government (public)
policies
with these objectives, as well as to changes in market signals and thus
responses of both the supply and the demand sides of the market. The
growing
demand for organic and environmentally freindly food production is
having
an effect in the market, encouraging more of these production
practices,
as well as generating pressure for government legislation and policies.
The market system, in spite of its apparent
concentration
on pure self-interest, does generate responses to changing
circumstances
and conditions and encourage socially acceptable solutions - albeit not
nearly fast enough or effectively enough for some peoples' tastes. It
is
a serious mistake, though, to consider government or state action and
management
of the social and economic system as an alternative to the
market
system. Both require each other.
Markets need to take account of public opinions
and
values, or the public will find ways (through government or through
their
own purchasing and factor supply decisions) to make markets behave
better.
But governments (and the general public) need also to take account of
the
expressions of self-interest and self-determination as expressed in
market
transactions, otherwise their attempts at governance and regulation are
quite likely to result in worse rather than better outcomes. Adam
Smith's
invisible hand is inevitably attached to the long arm of the law - to
enforce
market contracts and protect property rights, and also to try and
correct
the market-determined income and wealth distributions between people so
that they accord more clearly with public perceptions of social justice.
The key difficulty, here, is that interference
with
the market distribution will tend to change incentives and market
signals,
and make the market work less well than if there is no interference. If
income (and associated consumption) and profit are the only motivators
of human activity, then this adverse effect on the market might be
serious.
However, there is both good reason and substantial evidence that people
do things for reasons other then pure economic self-interest (though
these
other motivations and behaviours have not yet been incorporated into
the
economic models and pictures of behaviours).
A note on the Meaning of "Competitive Markets" in the textbooks
The typical textbook definition of perfect competition
includes:
- freedom of information (perfect information)
- freedom of entry and exit to markets and trade
- many buyers and many sellers
- homogenous products (one unit cannot be distinguished from
another)
- private costs and benefits should be equal to public or social
costs
and
benefits. Thus, the gains (or costs) to society are exactly represented
by the sum of all gains and costs to individuals and private firms.
We have already dealt with all of these conditions except the
first.
We have seen (under monopoly) how restricted entry to markets creates
monopolies
( a single seller), and the possibility of supernormal or monoply
profits.
And we have seen how the operation of market competition for these
profits
is likely to errode the profit. We have seen how markets tend to
deal with homogenous products - by differentiating them, to produce
monopolistic
competition. And we have just dealt with the issues arising from
private costs and benefits differing from their public or social
counterparts
- the market failures of public goods and externalities, and we have
seen
that, at least in principle though not so easily in practice, it is
possible
for people to get together and sort out these problems for themselves -
through market transactions and contracts - on the basis of trades and
trade-offs between what we want and what we can get.
What about Perfect information? Clearly the concept of
completely perfect information is perfectly stupid - no-one can know
the
future, so information can never be perfect since it cannot include
fore-knowledge.
The collection and organisation of information, so that it can be used
to generate knowledge, is (at least in part) an economic activity - it
uses and needs time, effort and resources, so will cost somebody
something
for which they will need to be re-imbursed, otherwise they will not be
able to continue doing it. So perfect information cannot mean that it
is
free either. So what do we mean by perfect information?
Essentially, we mean that all sides of the market (buyers and
sellers
and traders) have equal access to all the available information
relating
to the market and its supply and demand conditions. Whether or not all
sides of the market then choose to make use of this information, and
how
individuals or firms choose to use it, is then up to them. However,
those
who make the best use of the available information (in the sense that
they
use it to better understand the consequences of their and others
actions)
will tend to prosper, while those who choose to ignore it will tend
(except
by fortunate accident) to do less well. So long as information on who
is
doing well and the ways in which they are using the information are
common
knowledge, then there is a built-in incentive to both follow best
practice
and to cooperate (trade) in information.
Collusion and exclusion of people or firms from the information pool
(which is frequently attempted by some in order to enhance their own
position
relative to others) is thus judged by this criterion to be
anti-competitive.
Note, here, that some commentaries and analyses of competitiveness seem
to imply that protection of information (exclusion of potential
competitors
from your own knowledge) is an important source of competitive
advantage
(not to be confused with comparative advantage). The argument
here
is that this activity is contrary to perfect competition, and therefore
should be regarded as a form of market failure. Governments
should
take all possible steps to ensure that information is freely available
to all.
However, this gives rise to very substantial problem - information
is a Public Good - my use of it does not deny you the use of the
same
information, and excluding you from its use amounts to a market
failure.
So, we need cooperative and collective decisions to spend the time and
resources necessary to generate information and organise it into
knowledge.
Which seems to mean that we will need government to help us do
this.
Privatisation of information is bad news for competition, and is bad
news
for the proper functioning of markets. Yet much of our market
systems
rely on people and firms laying personal or private claim to
information
and knowledge - patents, copyrights, intellectual property rights (as
they
are frequently called) - as licences to earn supernormal profits,
justified
on the grounds that it costs money and resources to produce it. I
regard this as the critical problem of our modern economies, but you
will
not find it much discussed in most of the introductory economic
textbooks.
In short - the traditional textbook definition of perfect
competition
is rather meaningless - it is not perfect in any sensible sense of the
word, and it is incomplete as an explanation of competition. So
why
does it persist? Because it allows for the more or less exact
(mathematical)
definition of a particularly abstract and very simple economy, from
which
some more or less rigorous conclusions can be drawn, most of which have
very little relevance to the real world. Which is why these notes
pay limited attention to the notion of perfect competition.
What should you have learned from this section?
- Market failures happen because of
- Public Goods
- Externalities
- Public goods are Non Rival and Non Excludable - meaning that
private
companies
will find it difficult to earn their livings from their production, and
some collective or public action is required - the government is
expected
to (help) provide them.
- Public Goods are different from Merit Goods, which also tend to
be
provided
by the "public sector" (Government)
- Externalities arise when by-products of market transactions
(supply or
demand) activities are uncompensated or unrewarded through market
exchange
- The key causes of externalities are:
- high transaction and negotiation costs (including the
difficulties of
estimating
the extra-market social costs or benefits of the activity)
- ill-defined or non-existent property rights
- Externalities prompt people to search for solutions, either by
clubing
together in non-governmental organisations (NGOs) such as the RSPB, or
by demanding government regulation and management of the associated
markets.
- Governments and markets are both part of the same complex of
human
interaction
and exchange - neither makes much sense without the other.
Microeconomics
deals with markets. Macroeconomics turns our attention to
governments
and their economic behaviour. Belief in the market system does
not
imply that governments are bad for economies - the very reverse -
government
are absolutely necessary for the proper functioning of markets.
Final Point: These
so-called market failures
might equally well be termed public
choice failures or political
failures. The fact that the market mechanisms do not take
full account of either the value of public goods or of externalities
can be interpreted as saying that the benefits of trying to account for
these features of our economic activity simply do not outweigh the very
considerable transaction and decision making costs associated
with finding their solution - hence markets do not bother to try and
solve them - the effort is not worth while. If this is true, then
the real challenge is to encourage more participatory democracy - more collective involvement in public decisions
- to reduce the transaction and decision making costs, and very
possibly improve the quality of public decisions. For examples of
what this might mean in practice, see the UN Local
Leadership Programme - especially their Best Practice - Good
Urban Governance Theme.
SO - WHAT ARE WE SUPPOSED TO
DO ABOUT THESE 'FAILURES'? - ESPECIALLY CLIMATE CHANGE - THE
MAJOR CHALLENGE FACING HUMAN SOCIETY? - SEE HERE FOR SOME DISCUSSION.
Back to the top
Return to ACE8015 index
Comments
or questions?